The following is a summary of chapter 8 of Metaphysics by Micheal Loux. The question of the chapter is: How does a material object (or concrete particular), if there is such a thing, persist through time? There are two views: Endurantism and Perdurantism
Endurantists claim that for a concrete particular to persist through time is for it to exist wholly and completely at different times. The account assumes a presentist account of time where what exists is real if and only if it exists at the present time. An entity overtime persists as numerically identical thing at one time as any other time. According to endurantists, concrete particulars do not have temporal parts. The only things that count as parts are those within space.
Perdurantists claim that it is not possible for numerically identical concrete particulars to exist at different times. Rather Perdurantists claim that a concrete particular is an aggregate of different parts each existing at its own time. Perdurantists assume an eternalist conception of time (and endorse a B-theory of time whereby there are no “tensed facts”) – time is a real dimension much like the three spatial dimensions and or entities are equally real at all times. An entity persists through time as temporal parts (or “time-slices”) of a concrete particular. Concrete particulars, on this view, are often depicted as “space-time worms” with all that exists at all times being equally real.
A perdurantist will also be committed to what van Inwagen calls universalism. Universalism is the view that “for any set, S, of disjoint objects, there is an object that the members of S compose.”[1] For example, on this view there is an object composed of my shoe and Donald Trump’s hair.
Perdurantism might strike us as odd but it shouldn’t. Surely we can cut the universe into as many parts as it has and correlatively conjoin those parts. Crucially, all those ways of cutting up the universe (both cutting up ordinary objects into their component parts and joining ordinary objects with other objects to form other objects) are equally legitimate. There is, in principle, no privileged way to carve up the universe. What we do instead is to recognize objects (the ordinary objects like chairs and tables) because they exhibit spacio-temporal proximity and become familiar over time.
Indiscernibles, Identities and Descartes-minus.
The main argument perdurantists pose to endurantists is supposed to show that endurantism leads to a contradiction. The “Descartes-minus” thought experiment is both gruesome and effective. Before we think about Descartes we should consider a couple of ground rules. The first rule is the indiscernibility of identicals that states that numerical identity entails indiscernibility in properties. So, if x is identical with y, then all the properties of x are properties of y. The logical properties of numerical identity are:
Reflexivity: “for every object, x, x is numerically identical with x”
Symmetry: “if an object, x is numerically identical with an object, y, then y, in turn, is numerically identical with x”
Transitivity: “if a thing, x, is numerically identical with a thing, y, and y, in turn, is numerically identical with a thing, z, then x is numerically identical with z.”
Closely related is the following rule: If x is identical with y, then all the parts of x are parts of y. Thus, perdurantists will argue, if there is a change in parts, then the two objects are not identical.
So, here is the story. Descartes has an accident in which he loses his left hand. The accident takes place at t. So we have the following objects: “Descartes-before-t” – complete Descartes with all his parts, “Descartes-minus” – all of Descartes minus his left hand, and “Descartes-after-t” – Descartes after the accident. Of course if we have “Descartes-minus” we have “Descartes-minus-before-t” – all of Descartes minus his left hand before t and “Descartes-minus-after-t” – Descartes-minus after the accident.
Endurantists want to assume that Descartes survived the accident and is the same Descartes before and after the accident (call this Assumption (A)). So:
(1) Descartes-before-t is numerically identical with Descartes-after-t
Presumably both Descartes-before-t and Descartes-minus survive the accident. So:
(2) Descartes-minus-after-t is numerically identical with Descartes-minus-before-t
How are Descartes-after-t and Descartes-minus-after-t related? They are identical. They have identical parts. So:
(3) Descartes-after-t is numerically identical with Descartes-minus-after-t
So, given transitivity, we get:
(4) Descartes-before-t is numerically identical with Descartes-minus-before-t
But (4) is false. Recall the indiscernibility of identicals: “numerical identity entails indiscernibility in properties” If x is identical with y, then all the properties of x are properties of y. But Descartes-before-t does not have the same properties as Descartes-minus-before-t (one less hand, less mass, takes up different region of space) so:
(5) Descartes-before-t is not numerically identical with Descartes-minus-before-t
So, (4) and (5) are contradictory and endurantism is false.
Endurantists have provided a number of solutions. Here are some:
Mereological Essentialism – Deny Assumption (A). An object is numerically identical iff it has all its parts. The loss of one atom from the chair you are sitting on means the chair at t and the chair at t2 are not numerically identical. This claim involves the correlative claim that language of common speech is vague. What we mean by “the same table” in common speech is not what we would mean in philosophical speech. Philosophers use a particular precised speech (Chisholm). When we speak of tables in the precised speech we mean a succession of chairs, but in vague and common speech we can speak of the “same” table. Roderick Chisholm claimed that this won’t work for persons. Since persons have a unity of consciousness, we must either assume that “I” refers to an immaterial soul or that at least one part of the human body is essential to the persistence of the person (it could be one cell to which “I” refers).
Relative Identity Theory – Deny that numerical identity is the only identity game in town. Peter Geach argues for relative identity whereby the sameness of x and y depend on the answer to the question: same what? Kinds are more fundamental than properties and so identity is kind dependent. Consequently, Geach can deny that (4) follows from (1)-(3). The reason is that (1) – (3) are underdefined. We can only get (4) from (1) – (3) if the same identity holds for each relation otherwise transitivity does not hold from one to t’other. Is it the same human being (1) or the same material (2)? If one holds to a relative identity theory, one can say the following:
It is not true that Descartes-minus-after-t is the same human beings as Descartes-before-t. Descartes-minus-before-t is not a human being at all, but only a fragment of a human being. Before the amputation, there is just one human beings, and he has a left hand. Bet neither is it true that Descartes-after-t is the same collection of cells as Descartes-before-t. If it is appropriate to call these things collections of cells, then we have no option but to call the deficient collections of cells.[2]
Constitutionalist Account – Constitutionalists deny (3). There are two objects that coincide in the same region of space. This view considers the lump of matter and the human being to be two objects that occupy the same space (Corcoran). If one can avoid (3), then there is no need to hold to (4) and the contradiction is avoided.
Van Inwagen’s view – There is no such thing as Descartes-minus. This is an arbitrary object and there are no such things as a table-minus one leg (strictly, according to van Inwagen, there is no such thing as a table). There is such a thing as Descartes but not Descartes without his left hand. Once his left hand is gone, there is no such thing as his left hand. Before he loses his left hand there is no such thing as Descartes without his left hand. What follows is the denial of (2) that presupposes that before Descartes’ accident there was such a thing as Descartes without his left hand.
[1] Michael Rea, “In Defense of Mereological Universalism” in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (June 1998): Vol. 58, No. 2., 347.
[2] Loux, 254.